Tulane University’s environmental misconduct shows how weak fines fuel financial greed over public health and environmental protection

In a recently filed legal action by the United States Environmental Protection Agency (EPA), Tulane University, doing business as Tulane National Primate Research Center, stands accused of failing to make accurate hazardous waste determinations and incorrectly reporting certain substances as hazardous when they were not. The complaint, which culminated in a Consent Agreement and Final Order (CAFO), pinpoints how mislabeling chemicals such as sodium azide (P105) and potassium cyanide (P098) triggered allegations of non-compliance under the Resource Conservation and Recovery Act (RCRA). Ultimately, federal regulators concluded Tulane reported a greater quantity of potassium cyanide than it had actually generated; and similarly, incorrectly labeled sodium azide as a hazardous waste by using the wrong code for the waste in question. The result? A negotiated fine of $15,000.

At first glance, the penalty’s scale might appear modest—an institution incurring thousands of dollars in fines for incomplete or inaccurate labeling. But beneath these details lies a story of environmental oversight, profit-driven motives, and a broader system that regularly places communities and ecosystems at risk of mismanagement. Indeed, while Tulane University is better known as an educational institution, in this context it also fits the profile of a business entity subject to the regulatory compliance and enforcement landscape. And like so many corporate actors, Tulane found itself running afoul of oversight designed to protect human health and the environment.

The complaint frames Tulane’s alleged infractions as a microcosm of what happens when corporate or institutional processes for waste management go astray. Although Tulane’s case concerns a relatively isolated set of infractions, its details reflect a larger narrative about how hazardous waste oversight in the United States can be undermined by inadequate corporate diligence, insufficient accountability measures, and a global economic system operating under the imperatives of profit maximization.

As we delve deeper, we see glimmers of the same tactics and outcomes that characterize a broader phenomenon: powerful entities operating under neoliberal capitalism, which champions deregulation and unbridled markets, occasionally see fines as just part of the cost of doing business. For them, paying a penalty—especially a modest one—can be more convenient than adopting the full measure of compliance that regulators require. This pattern not only perpetuates environmental harm but also actively fosters wealth disparity, as corporate budgets and executive pay remain relatively unscathed while local communities often bear the brunt of any contamination or health risks.

In this investigative piece, we will examine the factual allegations set forth in the CAFO. We will also situate these allegations within a broader framework of corporate misconduct under late-stage capitalism—pointing to deregulation, regulatory capture, and the large-scale incentives that push corporations or institutions to skirt compliance for the sake of profit. In painting this bigger picture, we will merge the specific details of the Tulane case with established trends observed in corporate behavior. Our journey begins with a rigorous look at the heart of these allegations—what exactly Tulane is said to have done wrong, how, and why it matters.

Yet this is not merely about one institution. Rather, this case exemplifies how something as seemingly mundane as a mislabeled drum of chemical waste can open a window into a system where public health and environmental protections rest on precarious footing. By studying these details carefully, we will highlight the cracks in regulatory frameworks that were intended to shield the public, workers, and ecosystems from long-term hazards.

Before we proceed, a few words on scope: This article relies on the specific details contained in the EPA complaint and final order! Where those details end, we will broaden the focus to show how this pattern of corporate conduct plays out in other areas, from the vantage of corporate social responsibility, economic fallout, corporate accountability, and the often ambivalent role of government oversight. While this piece digs into the complexities of the Tulane matter, it also stands as a testament to the systemic challenges we face in a neoliberal economic order that frequently puts profit above public health.


Corporate Intent Exposed

The EPA’s case against Tulane University, operating as the Tulane National Primate Research Center, boils down to allegations of mismanagement under RCRA, a federal law designed to ensure the safe treatment, storage, and disposal of hazardous waste in the United States. The complaint specifically identifies how Tulane’s facility, a biomedical research institution, wrongly labeled certain wastes and generated inaccurate manifests.

Tulane had labeled sodium azide (P105) as a hazardous waste when, in fact, the mixture at issue did not meet the definition of a P-listed hazardous waste because sodium azide was not the “sole active ingredient.” The mislabeling was essentially an overreporting of hazard. In addition, Tulane reported having disposed of a much larger quantity of potassium cyanide (P098) waste than it had actually generated—two kilograms of potassium cyanide recorded, versus the actual 0.025 kilograms across a couple of containers.

On paper, these might sound like garden-variety administrative errors. However, to regulators, accurate labeling and proper manifesting are cornerstones of RCRA compliance. The labeling determines which set of safety precautions must be followed from “cradle to grave.” The shipping manifest, in turn, ensures transparency in where waste is transported and disposed of. When these systems are gamed or incorrectly administered—intentionally or not—they compromise the entire chain of accountability, threatening worker safety, community health, and the environment.

The complaint acknowledges that Tulane, upon being alerted, cooperated with the EPA’s investigation and sought to remedy its processes. Yet it is instructive to note how the allegations point to an institutional shortcoming: there was some internal breakdown that allowed misidentification of waste. Whether due to negligence or oversight, the facility ended up generating hazardous waste manifests that were not only inaccurate but also fundamentally misaligned with federal law.

In the world of corporate misconduct, errors can often blur the line between innocent mistake and willful evasion. Was Tulane’s incorrect labeling an intentional attempt to reduce the burden of compliance, or was it simply an oversight in a complex system? The complaint refrains from labeling the facility’s actions as deliberate fraud. Yet in the broader context of for-profit models (and yes, universities can be quite profit-oriented in their research arms), many institutions have an incentive to cut corners.

Examining the complaint, we glean some basic corporate strategies at play, even if they are not explicitly enumerated in the legal documents. For instance, if hazardous waste is mischaracterized—whether as more or less dangerous than it really is—it can impact disposal costs, public transparency, and liability exposure. Typically, classifying a substance as hazardous entails higher disposal expenditures and more rigorous compliance steps. Conversely, incorrectly labeling a truly dangerous substance as benign can reduce immediate overhead but create long-term liabilities. In Tulane’s situation, the mislabeling ironically overestimated hazard for sodium azide while possibly preventing a precise and direct regulatory approach to the actual quantity of potassium cyanide.

Regardless of the impetus for such mislabeling, the outcome is the same: inaccurate recordkeeping that can undermine community trust in how a facility handles substances that could contaminate soil, groundwater, or air. These allegations, though specific to Tulane, highlight how easily corporate or institutional compliance can falter. Whether for cost savings, confusion over standards, or the sheer complexity of waste management protocols, the pattern reveals systemic vulnerabilities.

Indeed, this is how corporate intent is often “exposed”: not in the brazen, cloak-and-dagger conspiracies we might see in Hollywood scripts, but rather in the day-to-day, behind-the-scenes processes that shape real-world operations. It is in these everyday decisions—choosing how to classify waste, how to fill out a form—that systemic failures fester.

The heart of the Tulane matter is not that the institution stands accused of polluting the earth with millions of gallons of toxic sludge. Instead, it is that the system entrusted with preventing such pollution relies on a labyrinth of classification codes, paperwork, and self-reporting. When that system fails—whether in a big or small way—it is everyday people, communities, and the environment that stand to lose. Tulane may have collaborated in remedying these oversights, but the question remains: why did such mismanagement occur in the first place, and what does it portend for other corporate actors navigating similar regulatory frameworks?


The Corporations Get Away With It

To fully appreciate how corporations (and, by extension, large institutions) can sidestep or minimize compliance, one must first understand the mechanics of environmental regulation in the United States. The Resource Conservation and Recovery Act has historically been revered—and sometimes loathed—for imposing comprehensive “cradle-to-grave” management of hazardous waste. Corporations are expected to meticulously identify, label, store, transport, and dispose of these materials in a manner that does not endanger public health or the environment.

However, the same labyrinthine regulations can facilitate loopholes. Self-reporting remains a key element of RCRA’s oversight mechanism. Federal agencies often rely on institutions to accurately self-disclose details about their waste streams. Enforcement agencies like the EPA have limited resources, meaning that not every site can be constantly monitored for compliance. This dynamic offers an opening for any entity—be it a large chemical conglomerate or a research-focused institution—to cut corners, even inadvertently, without immediate detection.

In Tulane’s case, the legal complaint revolves around inaccuracies in labeling and manifesting. While these inaccuracies might seem mild at first, they strike at the heart of the self-reporting model. If an institution can neglect its waste management responsibilities and remain undetected until a routine inspection or investigation, then it stands to reason that many others could do the same. In a setting dominated by profit motives (or budgetary pressures in the case of institutions), the impetus to reduce costs or streamline processes can easily outweigh the moral and ethical imperative to align with regulations.

One consistent pattern, often overlooked, is that even when violations are caught, the penalties can be modest relative to the size of the enterprise in question. A $15,000 penalty might sting, but for a well-funded research institution, or for a multinational corporation, that penalty could be viewed as negligible—just another line item in a budget that includes billions in annual revenue or hundreds of millions in research funding. Economically speaking, a penalty on this scale often fails to serve as a disincentive against future misconduct.

Compounding the problem, many corporations have developed sophisticated legal strategies to push back against regulatory action. They may negotiate fines down or stall proceedings for years. While the Tulane case ended in a consent agreement without lengthy litigation, plenty of examples across various industries demonstrate how well-heeled corporate law firms can poke holes in regulatory claims, exhaust appeals, or settle on terms that appear beneficial to the violator.

Regulatory capture also rears its head. When agencies tasked with enforcement are underfunded, politically influenced, or reliant on industry expertise, the notion of truly disinterested oversight becomes compromised. Politically, neoliberal capitalism thrives on the promise that deregulated markets can police themselves or that minimal government intervention is best for economic growth. But in practice, this environment can create a culture of compliance avoidance—because, from a purely fiscal standpoint, it may be cheaper to pay the occasional fine than invest in robust compliance systems.

Add to that the public-relations dimension. Corporations often react to allegations of misconduct by crafting statements that emphasize their commitment to “corporate social responsibility,” sustainability, and ethical conduct. Indeed, if they do release a statement, it may stress that the matter was simply an administrative oversight or an isolated event. In other words, by controlling the narrative, they distance themselves from accountability.

The outcome? To the average onlooker, Tulane’s mislabeling might appear as a technical or benign mistake that was quickly resolved, as if no harm was truly done. But from a systemic viewpoint, it reveals how institutions “get away with it” time and time again. If the system fails to impose penalties commensurate with the risk posed to public health and the environment, corporations or institutions see little incentive to fundamentally alter their practices. And so, the cycle repeats.

The lesson is maddening: Because the penalty for non-compliance may pale in comparison to the cost of robust compliance, organizations often act out of economic self-interest rather than moral responsibility. This problem intensifies in industries or research sectors where specialized knowledge can shield wrongdoing from easy detection. Put simply, it’s hard for regulators to tell whether your waste streams are properly labeled if the chemistry is complex and you’re the only one who fully understands it.

In an era of expanding corporate reach, the stakes have never been higher. Tulane’s transgression might be small relative to headline-grabbing environmental disasters, but in its ordinariness, it underscores a broader pattern: compliance systems built on self-policing are susceptible to manipulation. And when that manipulation is discovered, the cost to the violators frequently remains minimal, making it easy for them to treat fines and settlements as a routine expense in the quest for growth.


The Cost of Doing Business

At the heart of many corporate misdeeds is a simple calculus: if the potential profit or cost saving from cutting a corner outweighs the likely regulatory fine, then compliance becomes optional. In effect, the penalty transforms into just another cost of doing business. The Tulane National Primate Research Center’s $15,000 fine exemplifies this phenomenon. Even though Tulane is not a classic profit-driven corporation in the sense of a stockholder-run enterprise, its business model for research can still involve substantial funding, budget allocations, and financial pressures—mirroring the typical dynamics in the corporate realm.

Under neoliberal capitalism, institutions are encouraged to streamline costs wherever possible. In a university setting, that might mean cutting corners in administrative overhead, including environmental compliance tasks. Here, the crucial question arises: How big a slice of the institution’s overall budget does robust environmental compliance actually consume, and how does that compare to the magnitude of the penalty for failing to meet those requirements? If the answer indicates that compliance is costlier than paying the occasional fine, the institution’s accountants might well shrug and proceed with minimal compliance.

Another dimension to consider is the intangible cost of reputational harm. For some corporations, brand perception is paramount. A single widely publicized scandal can derail an entire corporate identity. But for a research institution like Tulane, the reputational calculus is more complicated. On one hand, a fiasco over hazardous waste might undermine public trust in the institution’s stewardship of health-related research. On the other hand, the specifics of the case may not command broad public attention. Without a strong wave of negative media coverage, the impetus to change might be limited.

Expanding this lens to a broader corporate world, we see that many companies willingly flirt with environmental infractions because the immediate financial gain overrides the risk. This is amplified by the reality that many corporate boards owe a fiduciary duty to maximize shareholder returns. When quarterly earnings weigh heavier than a potential environmental enforcement action down the road, short-term decision-making prevails.

Consequently, communities find themselves at the receiving end of this cost-benefit mismatch. Hazardous substances—be they incorrectly labeled chemicals in a research facility, industrial toxins from a manufacturing plant, or persistent pollutants from an energy company—lurk quietly in storage containers, potential ticking time bombs. If mismanaged or mislabeled, they pose real risks to groundwater, air quality, and human health. Children playing in nearby parks, workers handling these substances, or local ecosystems that sustain biodiversity can all suffer lasting harm.

Meanwhile, the corporate entity (or in this instance, the research institution) might see the penalty as a financial pittance. Indeed, a $15,000 fine likely constitutes a fraction of what might be allocated for a single piece of specialized laboratory equipment. For large corporations, the disparity between penalty amounts and corporate revenues grows even more pronounced—multi-billion-dollar giants occasionally pay fines in the mere millions, an amount easily absorbed by a day’s worth of global sales.

If we situate Tulane’s situation within the sweeping narrative of neoliberal capitalism, it becomes a microcosm illustrating how the system fosters these trade-offs. Deregulation, or under-enforcement, effectively emboldens corner-cutting. Regulatory capture ensures that even when laws are on the books, enforcement can be tepid. And corporations—driven by the need to meet profit projections—treat compliance as an afterthought unless or until a crisis pushes them into the spotlight.

Tulane, in this sense, represents both an outlier—because it is primarily an academic institution—and an exemplar, because it behaved in the manner often seen in for-profit settings: mismanaging regulatory obligations and only fully addressing them once the government steps in. Indeed, the embedded risk to public health stands as the real cost of doing business. While the dollar amount of a fine is quantifiable, the toll on local communities, workers, or ecosystems can be difficult to calculate but far more devastating in the long run.

In a society increasingly aware of ecological limits and social inequalities, the question becomes: How long can these trade-offs persist? If paying a fine continues to be cheaper than ensuring ironclad compliance, the cycle of minimal oversight—followed by revelations of wrongdoing—will continue. All too often, the monetary penalty levied fails to reflect the full extent of the damage inflicted upon public health and the environment. Until that changes, the cost of doing business will remain a grossly inadequate measure of accountability.


Systemic Failures

While Tulane’s mislabeling might appear to be an isolated event, it underscores fundamental weaknesses in the broader regulatory tapestry. One of the central tenets of RCRA is that institutions manage their hazardous waste accurately from cradle to grave—labeling it properly, storing it safely, and ensuring its eventual disposal in compliance with stringent environmental standards. Yet, as the Tulane case highlights, the system hinges heavily on internal reporting.

Where government agencies might ideally conduct thorough inspections of thousands upon thousands of facilities across the country, they often lack the manpower and budget to do so. This shortfall creates a gap in enforcement—a gap that is practically an invitation for mislabeling, underreporting, or mismanagement. In some instances, the mismanagement is inadvertent, driven by the complexity of regulations and the need for specialized knowledge about chemical properties. In other instances, it is more deliberate, an attempt to minimize the burdens of compliance.

Part of the problem stems from how budgets are allocated for environmental oversight. In many political climates, funding for the EPA or state environmental agencies can be inconsistent or prone to cuts, reinforcing a reliance on self-policing. If an entity—be it a university lab or a major multinational—knows inspectors come knocking only rarely, the temptation to remain lax on compliance grows stronger.

Furthermore, the legal system can inadvertently facilitate minimal accountability. While the RCRA is robust in principle, the scale of fines and the frequency of prosecutions vary widely. Companies or institutions that do face enforcement actions often negotiate consent agreements, as Tulane did, thereby avoiding protracted litigation. These agreements can spare both parties time and resources but may also fail to produce the kind of punitive bite that shapes corporate behavior.

Even more concerning is the phenomenon of “revolving doors” and regulatory capture. In some sectors, industry experts migrate into regulatory bodies, or vice versa. Their expertise can be invaluable but also fosters a culture of leniency. Decisions may be colored by an empathetic stance toward corporations attempting to eke out profit or maintain tight budgets. Over time, the emphasis shifts away from rigorous enforcement to “business-friendly” approaches that revolve around voluntary disclosures and negotiated settlements.

Under a neoliberal capitalist framework, this dynamic amplifies exponentially. The central assumption is that markets can largely govern themselves and that regulation is best kept minimal. In theory, such minimal intervention fosters innovation and economic growth. In reality, it frequently ushers in a climate where cost-cutting overshadows public welfare. Meanwhile, communities and workers—those most likely to suffer from environmental hazards—lack the resources or political clout to hold violators accountable.

Hence, the Tulane scenario mirrors a structural reality. When the institution mislabeled potassium cyanide, the only real impetus for correction arose when an external body (the EPA) took notice. Otherwise, the mistake, whether intentional or not, might have quietly continued. This scenario can recur across industries, from oil and gas to pharmaceuticals, each time posing a real threat to local environments.

The irony is that RCRA was introduced precisely to prevent such lapses. Yet the labyrinthine nature of the legislation and the scarcity of consistent enforcement ensure that even with RCRA in place, systemic failures persist. One might argue that the situation calls for more robust oversight, yet in an era of budget constraints and deregulation rhetoric, the path toward stronger enforcement is far from certain.

Indeed, the complexities of a globalized economy also stymie efforts at accountability. The transnational reach of many corporations enables them to shop for the weakest regulatory environments and to obscure supply chains. While Tulane’s case remains domestic, plenty of real-world scenarios show how hazardous waste might quietly travel offshore to countries with more lax regulations, compounding the scale of environmental injustice.

In sum, the allegations laid out against Tulane are not just a curiosity for legal scholars or environmental activists; they serve as a microcosm of a bigger puzzle. The fundamental premise of self-reporting, combined with sporadic enforcement, creates an environment rife with risk. Until we grapple with the overarching reality of neoliberal capitalism and the shortfalls it imposes on environmental governance, we will continue witnessing the type of misconduct that rears its head in incidents like Tulane’s.


This Pattern of Predation Is a Feature, Not a Bug

After sifting through the details of Tulane’s alleged lapses, it is tempting to dismiss them as mere oversights by a research institution. But in the broader world of corporate ethics and environmental management, the pattern is both more insidious and systematic. Indeed, under neoliberal capitalism, the drive to place corporate growth—and by extension, institutional expansion—above all else often manifests in decisions that privilege profit over social responsibility.

One might question why an educational institution would ever willfully engage in misconduct. Yet universities, particularly those that house robust research operations, frequently rely on grants, third-party funding, and partnerships with private industries. The impetus to keep overheads low, expedite research timelines, and impress potential funders can create a culture that deprioritizes thorough compliance. When environmental regulations get in the way, corners may be cut.

Labeling mistakes—like overreporting the quantity of potassium cyanide—could obscure deeper issues about how the institution manages hazardous chemicals in total. If mislabeling was discovered in one area, could similar missteps exist in others? The complaint focuses on the specific oversight that was documented, but it rarely ends with just one mislabel. Under neoliberal capitalism, such behavior is less an aberration and more a predictable outcome of the system’s profit-driven logic.

In a corporate world, and increasingly in the realm of large institutions, short-term financial or operational gains are often valued above long-term public good. This dynamic is precisely why experts refer to such predatory patterns as a “feature” of the system, not a bug. When it is more cost-effective to quietly mislabel or underreport waste, the system inadvertently rewards that behavior—at least until a regulator shows up. And when the penalty is relatively small, the net benefit might still tilt toward minimal compliance.

Such patterns reverberate well beyond the gates of any single research center or corporate headquarters. Communities bear the brunt of toxins that can seep into soil and water. Workers face potential health hazards if they come into contact with mislabeled or poorly stored chemicals. Local health systems can eventually grapple with the fallout, whether it manifests in elevated cancer rates or other long-term conditions.

Meanwhile, wealth disparity widens as corporations (or wealthy institutions) leverage their resources to absorb occasional fines, while smaller entities or frontline communities lack the means to respond effectively. The system thrives on these inequities, ensuring that those with power or capital can afford to take risks—be they legal, environmental, or social—while those without remain disproportionately vulnerable.

Tulane’s alleged wrongdoing, then, underscores a universal story about how institutions of any stripe can be entwined in the logic of neoliberal capitalism. While we might expect more from an institution whose mission often includes public service, the reality is that these large research centers operate with budgets, expansions, and partnership imperatives that mirror corporate strategies. The same incentives to externalize costs—be they environmental or social—operate here as in any large-scale economic enterprise.

But calling this pattern “predatory” might strike some as harsh. After all, Tulane’s mislabeling does not appear to have led to any documented health crisis or catastrophic spill. However, the real significance lies in what such infractions indicate: a system in which regulations meant to protect the environment and public health are no match for the complexities, loopholes, and cost calculations that guide institutional decision-making.

It is this embedded dynamic—where short-term gains overshadow the very regulations designed to defend human well-being—that makes repeated instances of misconduct feel inevitable. Until there is a comprehensive restructuring of the incentives and frameworks that guide institutional behavior, we can expect to see more of the same. When the reward for circumventing or fudging the rules outweighs the penalty, not only is this pattern predictable, but it is practically guaranteed.


The PR Playbook of Damage Control

Corporations, universities, and other large organizations have long learned that once wrongdoing surfaces, controlling the narrative becomes paramount. Whether it’s an oil spill, a data breach, or (in Tulane’s case) a mislabeling under RCRA, the institution’s communications team quickly goes into damage control. The overarching objective: reassure stakeholders—regulators, investors, donors, students, and the general public—that the situation is under control and does not reflect a deeper ethical failing.

In standard practice, the organization might release a carefully worded statement explaining that the error was an isolated incident, perhaps caused by minor administrative oversights. It would likely outline steps taken to remedy the violations, such as enhanced staff training, an internal audit, or improvements in recordkeeping systems. The underlying message is always: “We’ve identified the issue; we’re fixing it; you can trust us again.”

The Tulane legal complaint notes that Tulane cooperated with the EPA’s investigation and ultimately consented to the final order, paying the agreed-upon penalty. This cooperation is typically a focal point for any PR statement. It emphasizes collaboration with regulators, painting the institution as earnest and responsible, even if the root cause was the institution’s own oversight.

But beneath the surface, these PR efforts can mask more entrenched problems. If the mislabeling incident stems from a culture of prioritizing speed over accuracy, or from management’s reluctance to invest in thorough compliance infrastructure, a press release alone will not rectify the deeper issues. PR statements rarely mention cost–benefit analyses that might have led to minimal compliance or administrative underfunding.

In some cases, organizations deploy philanthropic or community-oriented gestures to offset negative press. Environmental or social sustainability initiatives, scholarship funds, or staff volunteer days can burnish the company or institution’s public image. While such efforts can be beneficial in their own right, they sometimes serve as strategic diversions, turning public attention toward the entity’s “good works” while overshadowing the systemic negligence at the core.

Furthermore, large institutions know the news cycle moves fast. A well-orchestrated PR campaign can rely on public fatigue and the ephemeral nature of media coverage. By the time deeper analyses of the regulatory complaint come to light, the public may have moved on, lulled by the next big story or headline scandal.

Another strategy might involve pivoting to a narrative of “corporate social responsibility,” highlighting how the institution invests in sustainable research, fosters diversity, or contributes philanthropic grants. These genuine or superficial acts can overshadow the reality that the same institution might cut corners in areas that do not draw direct public scrutiny, such as hazardous waste management.

Consequently, the PR playbook staves off reputational damage more effectively than many realize. It can also obscure meaningful accountability: if an institution can quell public outcry, there is often less impetus for regulators to push for harsher penalties or for activist groups to organize large-scale campaigns.

In Tulane’s case, the relative obscurity of a technical RCRA violation might have also insulated the institution from mass media scrutiny. Environmental compliance does not always pique public interest unless there is a catastrophic spill or immediate health hazard. That said, the mislabeling of hazardous waste is no small matter. Potassium cyanide, even in small quantities, is notably toxic. And while the complaint acknowledges that the actual amounts Tulane managed were less than reported, the fact that it was misreported signals a serious oversight.

Taken together, the damage control tactics revolve around controlling the immediate story, emphasizing cooperation and corrective measures, and reframing the institution as a well-intentioned entity that made an understandable mistake. This approach often works, particularly in a culture that seldom demands deeper institutional reforms unless a scandal reaches crisis proportions. As we will see, the power imbalance between corporate actors—armed with these sophisticated PR tools—and the communities that might be affected by environmental missteps illustrates the precarious balancing act of “corporate accountability” in a neoliberal era.


Corporate Power vs. Public Interest

At the crux of modern debates on corporate ethics is the tension between concentrated power in large institutions—be they commercial giants or influential universities—and the collective well-being of the public. For many watchers of environmental and labor issues, the scale appears heavily weighted in favor of corporate or institutional interests. This advantage extends to legal resources, lobbying influence, and relationships with regulatory bodies.

When allegations like those faced by Tulane surface, the question naturally arises: Who is looking out for the public interest? Environmental enforcement agencies are often under-resourced, meaning they must triage which violations to pursue. By the time they get around to investigating a given site, unreported infractions might have already taken their toll.

Moreover, the public typically lacks immediate access to the complex details of RCRA or other environmental laws. Even the complaint in Tulane’s case, though made publicly available, is legalistic and technical. Without specialized training, community members may find it challenging to interpret these documents, let alone mount a cohesive response.

The imbalance intensifies when we consider the potential consequences of these violations. Communities reliant on local aquifers for drinking water, or workers exposed to improperly labeled chemicals, bear the brunt of the risks. The entity at fault, on the other hand, typically has the resources to manage any fallout, including legal fees, PR, and negotiations with regulators.

Under a neoliberal capitalist framework, the impetus to protect the public interest can be compromised by “regulatory capture,” in which agencies form too-close relationships with the industries they regulate. In extreme cases, legislation may be shaped by corporate lobbyists to serve industry interests first, effectively relegating community well-being to a secondary concern. Even in less extreme scenarios, the underfunding or under-staffing of regulatory agencies leaves the public reliant on sporadic enforcement.

Take Tulane’s fine of $15,000. If the broader concern is safeguarding local communities from hazardous waste mismanagement, then a fine of that magnitude might fall short of fully compensating for the investigative time and resources spent by the EPA, let alone act as a deterrent. The institution is presumably able to absorb this cost with minimal disruption to its day-to-day operations. Meanwhile, the public is left hoping that Tulane’s compliance improvements—which the complaint mandates—are thorough enough to prevent future missteps.

Corporate power also manifests through what is sometimes called “administrative burden.” The complex forms and processes required for compliance can be intimidating to smaller entities or community groups trying to keep watch on local industries. But well-funded institutions can hire compliance officers, consultants, and attorneys to navigate or even exploit these layers of bureaucracy. Thus, the system’s complexity works both as a protective shield for corporate interests and a barrier to grassroots monitoring.

All these dynamics combine to paint a sobering picture of corporate accountability. Even in a case where the institution in question cooperates and pays a penalty, as Tulane did, the underlying structural imbalance remains. Without sustained vigilance from regulators and engaged citizenry, and without more robust financial penalties and criminal sanctions, organizations may continue to treat environmental infractions as acceptable risks.

Consequently, the tension between corporate power and public interest is not merely a philosophical debate. It is lived reality for neighborhoods near industrial zones, for employees handling chemicals, and for ecosystems that cannot protect themselves. Every mislabeling, every inaccurate manifest, every month of lax oversight adds another strain to the environment’s capacity to sustain life. And in the shadow of these large players, the public often finds itself scrambling just to understand the scope of potential harm.


The Human Toll on Workers and Communities

Although the Tulane complaint does not mention direct harm to any workers or local community members, the potential for human impact is woven into the fabric of hazardous waste management. Each chemical that is mislabeled, improperly handled, or lost in the shuffle of inaccurate recordkeeping could pose a threat to the people who work in or live near the facility.

Consider a lab technician disposing of what they think is a non-toxic substance, only to discover—perhaps too late—that the material contains dangerously high levels of a chemical like potassium cyanide. The ramifications could be immediate, such as acute poisoning, or insidiously long term, such as chronic health complications. The very reason RCRA imposes stringent rules for labeling and manifesting is to provide a line of defense for workers and handlers who interact with these chemicals.

In a community context, chemical mismanagement can escalate into significant local crises. For instance, if mislabeled waste is stored improperly, a leak or spill could contaminate groundwater. If a fire were to erupt in a storage area containing unknown chemicals, emergency responders would face an elevated risk, having limited awareness of what they are actually dealing with. In that sense, each step of the hazardous waste chain—generation, labeling, transportation, and disposal—represents a vital checkpoint in safeguarding human health.

Beyond the immediate physical risks, the social and economic implications can be vast. Communities forced to contend with an environmental hazard often suffer property value declines and face erosion of local trust in institutions. People might choose to relocate, fracturing community bonds and reducing local tax revenue. This cycle can spur a cascading effect where resources for schools, healthcare, and infrastructure dwindle, further exacerbating economic fallout and wealth disparity.

Neoliberal capitalism tends to accelerate this deterioration, as institutions often prioritize cost savings over robust environmental safeguards. While Tulane may be unique in that its mission is educational, the same incentive structures can still loom in the background. Saving on waste management might free up funds for other projects, or simply reduce budgetary pressures. But the cost in terms of human well-being is incalculable if errors in chemical handling lead to actual harm.

Moreover, the burden of such negligence tends to disproportionately fall on marginalized communities, a fact well-documented in studies of environmental justice. Industrial facilities, including research centers, are often located in or near neighborhoods with lower socioeconomic status or predominantly minority populations. These populations can face heightened vulnerability due to less political power, weaker access to healthcare, and fewer resources to confront polluters.

In the Tulane scenario, the complaint does not detail any injuries or direct community harm. But the potential risk, once these dangerous chemicals were mislabeled, is precisely why federal regulations are in place. The presence of substances like sodium azide and potassium cyanide underscores the kind of hazards that warrant exacting management standards. Any slip in following those standards puts people at risk.

Thus, the human toll might be invisible at this juncture—no dramatic headlines of mass poisoning or environmental calamity. But the underlying dynamic is still cause for concern: if a publicly visible institution like Tulane can lapse in its waste determinations, how many other facilities might be doing worse, with even less oversight? In a society marred by wealth disparity and corporate corruption, each new misstep adds to a tally of environmental injustices that primarily harm working-class communities and disproportionately impact those with the fewest resources for recourse.

Ultimately, the conversation about hazardous waste mismanagement must acknowledge this human dimension. Behind every mislabeled container or incorrectly completed manifest are people—workers, families, children—who rely on institutional compliance for their health and safety. The piece of paper that gets filled out incorrectly or the label that is affixed in error might appear trivial, but it can ripple outward, threatening life and livelihood in ways that are immeasurable when the risk turns into real harm.


Global Trends in Corporate Accountability

The Tulane matter might be unfolding within a single state in the U.S., but the issues it raises resonate with corporate accountability struggles around the globe. Under a neoliberal capitalist framework, major corporations—whether in manufacturing, energy, chemicals, or tech—have long sought to minimize the costs of environmental regulations. They move operations to jurisdictions with lax oversight, lobby for weaker rules, or exploit the complexity of compliance to obfuscate wrongdoing.

In many countries, the cultural and institutional structures that might hold these entities accountable are weaker still. While the EPA, despite its flaws, remains a robust regulatory body compared to its counterparts in certain developing nations, corporations can easily shift production or waste disposal offshore to sidestep even these minimal hurdles. The net result? A race to the bottom, where communities with the fewest resources become dumping grounds for hazardous waste.

Moreover, the same PR strategies that we see domestically replicate on an international stage. Companies pledge corporate social responsibility, sign on to voluntary accords, and release sustainability reports that often omit inconvenient truths. While these public-facing documents can talk at length about planting trees or hosting clean-up drives, the behind-the-scenes reality might include suppressed data on pollution or questionable disposal methods.

In the context of global trends, the mislabeling of hazardous substances such as potassium cyanide becomes just one thread in a much larger tapestry of corporate malfeasance. Similar or even more egregious examples abound internationally, where entire rivers have been contaminated by chemical leaks, and local populations forced to abandon ancestral lands.

These global parallels underscore the extent to which the Tulane incident is not a stray anomaly. The pattern of minimal enforcement, inadequate penalties, and cost-driven decision-making resonates everywhere. While the fines or regulatory details differ from country to country, the underlying logic remains the same: a system that prizes economic output and corporate expansion above the environment and public health.

However, there are glimmers of hope. Around the world, grassroots movements and NGOs are demanding stricter regulations and pushing for corporate accountability. International frameworks such as the Basel Convention attempt to regulate transboundary movements of hazardous wastes, though enforcement remains uneven. Growing public awareness of climate change and environmental justice issues also ratchets up the social cost of being caught in wrongdoing.

For institutions like Tulane, which have reputations to maintain, the global shift in attitudes toward environmental responsibility might exert pressure for better compliance. As donors, alumni, and professional bodies become more aware of these topics, the mere specter of negative publicity could force improvements. That said, the underlying neoliberal incentives remain powerful. Unless the cost of non-compliance climbs—through higher fines, reputational damage, or stringent regulation—these deeper structural challenges will persist.

Ultimately, the Tulane example reminds us that accountability is a universal concern. Whether in a Louisiana research facility or an overseas industrial plant, the push-and-pull between economic imperatives and environmental stewardship unfolds similarly. The lesson is consistent: as long as the system treats accountability as negotiable, the environment and human populations remain at risk.


Pathways for Reform and Consumer Advocacy

Reflecting on Tulane’s case and the broader systemic issues it illuminates, it becomes clear that a more effective system of checks and balances is needed. On the one hand, we must address the structural flaws of neoliberal capitalism that incentivize cutting corners for short-term gains. On the other hand, we require tangible reforms at the policy and enforcement levels—changes that will bolster corporate ethics, reduce wealth disparity, and safeguard public health.

One immediate reform could involve toughening the financial penalties for environmental violations. If the cost of fines dwarfs the savings a corporation might enjoy by skirting regulations, institutions become far less likely to take such risks. In addition, enforcement agencies must be adequately funded to conduct regular, unannounced inspections. While such measures might face resistance from those who argue they hamper economic growth, the long-term benefits—in terms of improved community health, environmental preservation, and corporate accountability—far outweigh the short-term costs.

Stricter personal liability for executives and managerial staff could also serve as a deterrent. In many large-scale pollution cases, corporate wrongdoing goes unpunished on an individual level. But if executives or high-level managers faced legal consequences for mismanagement—especially in repeated or severe cases—institutions would have stronger incentives to adopt a culture of compliance rather than pay lip service to corporate social responsibility.

Consumer advocacy plays a pivotal role, too. While Tulane might not be a consumer-facing corporation, broader parallels exist in industries where the public can use purchasing power and activism to force transparency. In an age of social media and instant communication, consumers who organize can bring about significant shifts in how companies account for their environmental impact. By choosing products from companies with credible sustainability records and calling out those that fail to meet basic standards, the broader public can push for corporate ethics and accountability.

For institutions like Tulane, stakeholder advocacy could come from alumni, students, or professional networks. These groups can demand accountability measures such as transparent reporting on all hazardous waste streams, third-party audits, and publication of compliance records. Public pressure also fosters a culture where the moral dimension of stewardship is emphasized: a research center should not only meet regulatory baselines but strive to set a high standard for environmental responsibility.

Additionally, new technologies and open-data initiatives can be leveraged to strengthen oversight. Real-time monitoring of waste streams, blockchain-based manifest tracking, and publicly accessible platforms for compliance data can prevent the kind of mislabeling we saw in Tulane’s case. By automating and digitizing parts of the compliance process, the margin for human error or deliberate misreporting shrinks.

Finally, all these efforts must be grounded in a moral reorientation that regards environmental health as inseparable from social justice. If the impetus for stronger regulation stems solely from a desire to avoid bad press or fines, the transformation will remain superficial. True progress emerges when communities, institutions, and governments recognize the intrinsic value of preserving ecosystems and protecting human lives—even when it might not directly boost a profit margin.

Tulane’s settlement might have closed the immediate chapter on this particular violation, but it opens a dialogue about how we can reimagine corporate responsibility, not only in educational institutions but across all sectors. In a world grappling with climate crises, pandemics, and systemic inequalities, the stakes are higher than ever. Hazardous waste mismanagement is a symptom of a larger malaise—a worldview that treats the environment as disposable. Reforming that worldview will require robust policy, collective action, and a rethinking of what economic success really means.


Tulane University’s website: https://tulane.edu/

You can read all about the lawsuit between the EPA and Tulane University here: https://yosemite.epa.gov/oa/rhc/epaadmin.nsf/Filings/FF564FC9E1B3972185258B79007E9833/$File/2024-0986.pdf

📢 Explore Corporate Misconduct by Category

🚨 Every day, corporations engage in harmful practices that affect workers, consumers, and the environment. Browse key topics: